Articles and book excerpts used in and referred to on Issues, Etc. |
The Lost Tools of Learning
by Dorothy Sayers
That I, whose experience
of teaching is extremely limited, should presume to discuss education is a
matter, surely, that calls for no apology. It is a kind of behavior to which
the present climate of opinion is wholly favorable. Bishops air their opinions
about economics; biologists, about metaphysics; inorganic chemists, about
theology; the most irrelevant people are appointed to highly technical
ministries; and plain, blunt men write to the papers to say that Epstein and
Picasso do not know how to draw. Up to a certain point, and provided that the
criticisms are made with a reasonable modesty, these activities are
commendable. Too much specialization is not a good thing. There is also one
excellent reason why the veriest amateur may feel entitled to have an opinion
about education. For if we are not all professional teachers, we have all, at
some time or another, been taught. Even if we learned nothingperhaps in
particular if we learned nothingour contribution to the discussion may
have a potential value.
However, it is in the highest degree
improbable that the reforms I propose will ever be carried into effect. Neither
the parents, nor the training colleges, nor the examination boards, nor the
boards of governors, nor the ministries of education, would countenance them
for a moment. For they amount to this: that if we are to produce a society of
educated people, fitted to preserve their intellectual freedom amid the complex
pressures of our modern society, we must turn back the wheel of progress some
four or five hundred years, to the point at which education began to lose sight
of its true object, towards the end of the Middle Ages.
Before you
dismiss me with the appropriate phrasereactionary, romantic,
mediaevalist, laudatory temporis acti (praiser of times past), or whatever tag
comes first to handI will ask you to consider one or two miscellaneous
questions that hang about at the back, perhaps, of all our minds, and
occasionally pop out to worry us.
When we think about the remarkably
early age at which the young men went up to university in, let us say, Tudor
times, and thereafter were held fit to assume responsibility for the conduct of
their own affairs, are we altogether comfortable about that artificial
prolongation of intellectual childhood and adolescence into the years of
physical maturity which is so marked in our own day? To postpone the acceptance
of responsibility to a late date brings with it a number of psychological
complications which, while they may interest the psychiatrist, are scarcely
beneficial either to the individual or to society. The stock argument in favor
of postponing the school-leaving age and prolonging the period of education
generally is there is now so much more to learn than there was in the Middle
Ages. This is partly true, but not wholly. The modern boy and girl are
certainly taught more subjectsbut does that always mean that they
actually know more?
Has it ever struck you as odd, or unfortunate,
that today, when the proportion of literacy throughout Western Europe is higher
than it has ever been, people should have become susceptible to the influence
of advertisement and mass propaganda to an extent hitherto unheard of and
unimagined? Do you put this down to the mere mechanical fact that the press and
the radio and so on have made propaganda much easier to distribute over a wide
area? Or do you sometimes have an uneasy suspicion that the product of modern
educational methods is less good than he or she might be at disentangling fact
from opinion and the proven from the plausible?
Have you ever, in
listening to a debate among adult and presumably responsible people, been
fretted by the extraordinary inability of the average debater to speak to the
question, or to meet and refute the arguments of speakers on the other side? Or
have you ever pondered upon the extremely high incidence of irrelevant matter
which crops up at committee meetings, and upon the very great rarity of persons
capable of acting as chairmen of committees? And when you think of this, and
think that most of our public affairs are settled by debates and committees,
have you ever felt a certain sinking of the heart?
Have you ever
followed a discussion in the newspapers or elsewhere and noticed how frequently
writers fail to define the terms they use? Or how often, if one man does define
his terms, another will assume in his reply that he was using the terms in
precisely the opposite sense to that in which he has already defined them? Have
you ever been faintly troubled by the amount of slipshod syntax going about?
And, if so, are you troubled because it is inelegant or because it may lead to
dangerous misunderstanding?
Do you ever find that young people, when
they have left school, not only forget most of what they have learnt (that is
only to be expected), but forget also, or betray that they have never really
known, how to tackle a new subject for themselves? Are you often bothered by
coming across grown-up men and women who seem unable to distinguish between a
book that is sound, scholarly, and properly documented, and one that is, to any
trained eye, very conspicuously none of these things? Or who cannot handle a
library catalogue? Or who, when faced with a book of reference, betray a
curious inability to extract from it the passages relevant to the particular
question which interests them?
Do you often come across people for
whom, all their lives, a subject remains a subject,
divided by watertight bulkheads from all other subjects, so that
they experience very great difficulty in making an immediate mental connection
between let us say, algebra and detective fiction, sewage disposal and the
price of salmonor, more generally, between such spheres of knowledge as
philosophy and economics, or chemistry and art?
Are you occasionally
perturbed by the things written by adult men and women for adult men and women
to read? We find a well-known biologist writing in a weekly paper to the effect
that: It is an argument against the existence of a Creator (I think
he put it more strongly; but since I have, most unfortunately, mislaid the
reference, I will put his claim at its lowest)--an argument against the
existence of a Creator that the same kind of variations which are produced by
natural selection can be produced at will by stock breeders. One might
feel tempted to say that it is rather an argument for the existence of a
Creator.
Actually, of course, it is neither; all it proves is that the
same material causes (recombination of the chromosomes, by crossbreeding, and
so forth) are sufficient to account for all observed variationsjust as
the various combinations of the same dozen tones are materially sufficient to
account for Beethovens Moonlight Sonata and the noise the cat makes by
walking on the keys. But the cats performance neither proves nor
disproves the existence of Beethoven; and all that is proved by the
biologists argument is that he was unable to distinguish between a
material and a final cause.
Here is a sentence from no less academic a
source than a front- page article in the Times Literary Supplement: The
Frenchman, Alfred Epinas, pointed out that certain species (e.g., ants and
wasps) can only face the horrors of life and death in association. I do
not know what the Frenchman actually did say; what the Englishman says he said
is patently meaningless. We cannot know whether life holds any horror for the
ant, nor in what sense the isolated wasp which you kill upon the window-pane
can be said to face or not to face the horrors of
death. The subject of the article is mass behavior in man; and the human
motives have been unobtrusively transferred from the main proposition to the
supporting instance. Thus the argument, in effect, assumes what it set out to
provea fact which would become immediately apparent if it were presented
in a formal syllogism. This is only a small and haphazard example of a vice
which pervades whole booksparticularly books written by men of science on
metaphysical subjects.
Another quotation from the same issue of the
TLS comes in fittingly here to wind up this random collection of disquieting
thoughtsthis time from a review of Sir Richard Livingstones
Some Tasks for Education: More than once the reader is
reminded of the value of an intensive study of at least one subject, so as to
learn the meaning of knowledge and what precision and persistence is
needed to attain it. Yet there is elsewhere full recognition of the distressing
fact that a man may be master in one field and show no better judgment than his
neighbor anywhere else; he remembers what he has learnt, but forgets altogether
how he learned it.
I would draw your attention particularly to
that last sentence, which offers an explanation of what the writer rightly
calls the distressing fact that the intellectual skills bestowed
upon us by our education are not readily transferable to subjects other than
those in which we acquired them: he remembers what he has learnt, but
forgets altogether how he learned it.
Is not the great defect of
our education todaya defect traceable through all the disquieting
symptoms of trouble that I have mentionedthat although we often succeed
in teaching our pupils subjects, we fail lamentably on the whole in
teaching them how to think: they learn everything, except the art of learning.
It is as though we had taught a child, mechanically and by rule of thumb, to
play The Harmonious Blacksmith upon the piano, but had never taught
him the scale or how to read music; so that, having memorized The
Harmonious Blacksmith, he still had not the faintest notion how to
proceed from that to tackle The Last Rose of Summer. Why do I say,
as though? In certain of the arts and crafts, we sometimes do
precisely thisrequiring a child to express himself in paint
before we teach him how to handle the colors and the brush. There is a school
of thought which believes this to be the right way to set about the job. But
observe: it is not the way in which a trained craftsman will go about to teach
himself a new medium. He, having learned by experience the best way to
economize labor and take the thing by the right end, will start off by doodling
about on an odd piece of material, in order to give himself the feel of
the tool.
Let us now look at the mediaeval scheme of
educationthe syllabus of the Schools. It does not matter, for the moment,
whether it was devised for small children or for older students, or how long
people were supposed to take over it. What matters is the light it throws upon
what the men of the Middle Ages supposed to be the object and the right order
of the educative process. The syllabus was divided into two parts: the Trivium
and Quadrivium. The second partthe Quadriviumconsisted of
subjects, and need not for the moment concern us. The interesting
thing for us is the composition of the Trivium, which preceded the Quadrivium
and was the preliminary discipline for it. It consisted of three parts:
Grammar, Dialectic, and Rhetoric, in that order.
Now the first thing
we notice is that two at any rate of these subjects are not what we
should call subjects at all: they are only methods of dealing with
subjects. Grammar, indeed, is a subject in the sense that it does
mean definitely learning a languageat that period it meant learning
Latin. But language itself is simply the medium in which thought is expressed.
The whole of the Trivium was, in fact,
intended to teach the pupil the proper use of the tools of learning, before
he began to apply them to subjects at all. First, he learned a
language; not just how to order a meal in a foreign language, but the structure
of a language, and hence of language itselfwhat it was, how it was put
together, and how it worked. Secondly, he learned how to use language; how to
define his terms and make accurate statements; how to construct an argument and
how to detect fallacies in argument. Dialectic, that is to say, embraced Logic
and Disputation. Thirdly, he learned to express himself in languagehow to
say what he had to say elegantly and persuasively.
At the end of his
course, he was required to compose a thesis upon some theme set by his masters
or chosen by himself, and afterwards to defend his thesis against the criticism
of the faculty. By this time, he would have learnedor woe betide
himnot merely to write an essay on paper, but to speak audibly and
intelligibly from a platform, and to use his wits quickly when heckled. There
would also be questions, cogent and shrewd, from those who had already run the
gauntlet of debate.
It is, of course, quite true that bits and pieces
of the mediaeval tradition still linger, or have been revived, in the ordinary
school syllabus of today. Some knowledge of grammar is still required when
learning a foreign languageperhaps I should say, is again
required, for during my own lifetime, we passed through a phase when the
teaching of declensions and conjugations was considered rather reprehensible,
and it was considered better to pick these things up as we went along. School
debating societies flourish; essays are written; the necessity for self-
expression is stressed, and perhaps even over-stressed. But these
activities are cultivated more or less in detachment, as belonging to the
special subjects in which they are pigeon-holed rather than as forming one
coherent scheme of mental training to which all subjects stand in a
subordinate relation. Grammar belongs especially to the
subject of foreign languages, and essay-writing to the
subject called English; while Dialectic has become
almost entirely divorced from the rest of the curriculum, and is frequently
practiced unsystematically and out of school hours as a separate exercise, only
very loosely related to the main business of learning. Taken by and large, the
great difference of emphasis between the two conceptions holds good: modern
education concentrates on teaching subjects, leaving the method of
thinking, arguing, and expressing ones conclusions to be picked up by the
scholar as he goes along mediaeval education concentrated on first
forging and learning to handle the tools of learning, using whatever subject
came handy as a piece of material on which to doodle until the use of the tool
became second nature.
Subjects of some kind there must be,
of course. One cannot learn the theory of grammar without learning an actual
language, or learn to argue and orate without speaking about something in
particular. The debating subjects of the Middle Ages were drawn largely from
theology, or from the ethics and history of antiquity. Often, indeed, they
became stereotyped, especially towards the end of the period, and the
far-fetched and wire-drawn absurdities of Scholastic argument fretted Milton
and provide food for merriment even to this day. Whether they were in
themselves any more hackneyed and trivial then the usual subjects set nowadays
for essay writing I should not like to say: we may ourselves grow a
little weary of A Day in My Holidays and all the rest of it. But
most of the merriment is misplaced, because the aim and object of the debating
thesis has by now been lost sight of.
A glib speaker in the Brains
Trust once entertained his audience (and reduced the late Charles Williams to
helpless rage) by asserting that in the Middle Ages it was a matter of faith to
know how many archangels could dance on the point of a needle. I need not say,
I hope, that it never was a matter of faith; it was simply a
debating exercise, whose set subject was the nature of angelic substance: were
angels material, and if so, did they occupy space? The answer usually adjudged
correct is, I believe, that angels are pure intelligences; not material, but
limited, so that they may have location in space but not extension. An analogy
might be drawn from human thought, which is similarly non-material and
similarly limited. Thus, if your thought is concentrated upon one
thingsay, the point of a needleit is located there in the sense
that it is not elsewhere; but although it is there, it occupies no
space there, and there is nothing to prevent an infinite number of different
peoples thoughts being concentrated upon the same needle-point at the
same time. The proper subject of the argument is thus seen to be the
distinction between location and extension in space; the matter on which the
argument is exercised happens to be the nature of angels (although, as we have
seen, it might equally well have been something else; the practical lesson to
be drawn from the argument is not to use words like there in a
loose and unscientific way, without specifying whether you mean located
there or occupying space there.
Scorn in plenty has
been poured out upon the mediaeval passion for hair-splitting; but when we look
at the shameless abuse made, in print and on the platform, of controversial
expressions with shifting and ambiguous connotations, we may feel it in our
hearts to wish that every reader and hearer had been so defensively armored by
his education as to be able to cry: Distinguo.
For we let
our young men and women go out unarmed, in a day when armor was never so
necessary. By teaching them all to read, we have left them at the mercy of the
printed word. By the invention of the film and the radio, we have made certain
that no aversion to reading shall secure them from the incessant battery of
words, words, words. They do not know what the words mean; they do not know how
to ward them off or blunt their edge or fling them back; they are a prey to
words in their emotions instead of being the masters of them in their
intellects. We who were scandalized in 1940 when men were sent to fight armored
tanks with rifles, are not scandalized when young men and women are sent into
the world to fight massed propaganda with a smattering of subjects;
and when whole classes and whole nations become hypnotized by the arts of the
spell binder, we have the impudence to be astonished. We dole out lip-service
to the importance of educationlip-service and, just occasionally, a
little grant of money; we postpone the school-leaving age, and plan to build
bigger and better schools; the teachers slave conscientiously in and out of
school hours; and yet, as I believe, all this devoted effort is largely
frustrated, because we have lost the tools of learning, and in their absence
can only make a botched and piecemeal job of it.
What, then, are we to
do? We cannot go back to the Middle Ages. That is a cry to which we have become
accustomed. We cannot go backor can we? Distinguo. I should like every
term in that proposition defined. Does go back mean a retrogression
in time, or the revision of an error? The first is clearly impossible per se;
the second is a thing which wise men do every day. Cannotdoes
this mean that our behavior is determined irreversibly, or merely that such an
action would be very difficult in view of the opposition it would provoke?
Obviously the twentieth century is not and cannot be the fourteenth; but if
the Middle Ages is, in this context, simply a picturesque phrase
denoting a particular educational theory, there seems to be no a priori reason
why we should not go back to itwith modificationsas we
have already gone back with modifications, to, let us say, the idea
of playing Shakespeares plays as he wrote them, and not in the
modernized versions of Cibber and Garrick, which once seemed to be
the latest thing in theatrical progress.
Let us amuse ourselves by
imagining that such progressive retrogression is possible. Let us make a clean
sweep of all educational authorities, and furnish ourselves with a nice little
school of boys and girls whom may experimentally equip for the intellectual
conflict along lines chosen by ourselves. We will endow them with exceptionally
docile parents; we will staff our school with teachers who are themselves
perfectly familiar with the aims and methods of the Trivium; we will have our
building and staff large enough to allow our classes to be small enough for
adequate handling; and we will postulate a Board of Examiners willing and
qualified to test the products we turn out. Thus prepared, we will attempt to
sketch out a syllabusa modern Trivium with modifications and
we will see where we get to.
But first: what age shall the children
be? Well, if one is to educate them on novel lines, it will be better that they
should have nothing to unlearn; besides, one cannot begin a good thing too
early, and the Trivium is by its nature not learning, but a preparation for
learning. We will, therefore, catch em young, requiring of
our pupils only that they shall be able to read, write, and cipher.
My
views about child psychology are, I admit, neither orthodox nor enlightened.
Looking back upon myself (since I am the child I know best and the only child I
can pretend to know from inside) I recognize three states of development.
These, in a rough-and- ready fashion, I will call the Poll-Parrot, the Pert,
and the Poeticthe latter coinciding, approximately, with the onset of
puberty. The Poll-Parrot stage is the one in which learning by heart is easy
and, on the whole, pleasurable; whereas reasoning is difficult and, on the
whole, little relished. At this age, one readily memorizes the shapes and
appearances of things; one likes to recite the number-plates of cars; one
rejoices in the chanting of rhymes and the rumble and thunder of unintelligible
polysyllables; one enjoys the mere accumulation of things. The Pert age, which
follows upon this (and, naturally, overlaps it to some extent), is
characterized by contradicting, answering back, liking to catch people
out (especially ones elders); and by the propounding of conundrums.
Its nuisance-value is extremely high. It usually sets in about the Fourth Form.
The Poetic age is popularly known as the difficult age. It is
self-centered; it yearns to express itself; it rather specializes in being
misunderstood; it is restless and tries to achieve independence; and, with good
luck and good guidance, it should show the beginnings of creativeness; a
reaching out towards a synthesis of what it already knows, and a deliberate
eagerness to know and do some one thing in preference to all others. Now it
seems to me that the layout of the Trivium adapts itself with a singular
appropriateness to these three ages: Grammar to the Poll-Parrot, Dialectic to
the Pert, and Rhetoric to the Poetic age.
Let us begin, then, with
Grammar. This, in practice, means the grammar of some language in particular;
and it must be an inflected language. The grammatical structure of an
uninflected language is far too analytical to be tackled by any one without
previous practice in Dialectic. Moreover, the inflected languages interpret the
uninflected, whereas the uninflected are of little use in interpreting the
inflected. I will say at once, quite firmly, that the best grounding for
education is the Latin grammar. I say this, not because Latin is traditional
and mediaeval, but simply because even a rudimentary knowledge of Latin cuts
down the labor and pains of learning almost any other subject by at least fifty
percent. It is the key to the vocabulary and structure of all the Teutonic
languages, as well as to the technical vocabulary of all the sciences and to
the literature of the entire Mediterranean civilization, together with all its
historical documents.
Those whose pedantic preference for a living
language persuades them to deprive their pupils of all these advantages might
substitute Russian, whose grammar is still more primitive. Russian is, of
course, helpful with the other Slav dialects. There is something also to be
said for Classical Greek. But my own choice is Latin. Having thus pleased the
Classicists among you, I will proceed to horrify them by adding that I do not
think it either wise or necessary to cramp the ordinary pupil upon the
Procrustean bed of the Augustan Age, with its highly elaborate and artificial
verse forms and oratory. Post-classical and mediaeval Latin, which was a living
language right down to the end of the Renaissance, is easier and in some ways
livelier; a study of it helps to dispel the widespread notion that learning and
literature came to a full stop when Christ was born and only woke up again at
the Dissolution of the Monasteries.
Latin should be begun as early as
possibleat a time when inflected speech seems no more astonishing than
any other phenomenon in an astonishing world; and when the chanting of
Amo, amas, amat is as ritually agreeable to the feelings as the
chanting of eeny, meeny, miney, moe.
During this age we
must, of course, exercise the mind on other things besides Latin grammar.
Observation and memory are the faculties most lively at this period; and if we
are to learn a contemporary foreign language we should begin now, before the
facial and mental muscles become rebellious to strange intonations. Spoken
French or German can be practiced alongside the grammatical discipline of the
Latin.
In English, meanwhile, verse and prose can be learned by heart,
and the pupils memory should be stored with stories of every
kindclassical myth, European legend, and so forth. I do not think that
the classical stories and masterpieces of ancient literature should be made the
vile bodies on which to practice the techniques of Grammarthat was a
fault of mediaeval education which we need not perpetuate. The stories can be
enjoyed and remembered in English, and related to their origin at a subsequent
stage. Recitation aloud should be practiced, individually or in chorus; for we
must not forget that we are laying the groundwork for Disputation and
Rhetoric.
The grammar of History should consist, I think, of dates,
events, anecdotes, and personalities. A set of dates to which one can peg all
later historical knowledge is of enormous help later on in establishing the
perspective of history. It does not greatly matter which dates: those of the
Kings of England will do very nicely, provided that they are accompanied by
pictures of costumes, architecture, and other everyday things, so that the mere
mention of a date calls up a very strong visual presentment of the whole
period.
Geography will similarly be presented in its factual aspect,
with maps, natural features, and visual presentment of customs, costumes,
flora, fauna, and so on; and I believe myself that the discredited and
old-fashioned memorizing of a few capitol cities, rivers, mountain ranges,
etc., does no harm. Stamp collecting may be encouraged.
Science, in
the Poll-Parrot period, arranges itself naturally and easily around
collectionsthe identifying and naming of specimens and, in general, the
kind of thing that used to be called natural philosophy. To know
the name and properties of things is, at this age, a satisfaction in itself; to
recognize a devils coach-horse at sight, and assure ones foolish
elders, that, in spite of its appearance, it does not sting; to be able to pick
out Cassiopeia and the Pleiades, and perhaps even to know who Cassiopeia and
the Pleiades were; to be aware that a whale is not a fish, and a bat not a
birdall these things give a pleasant sensation of superiority; while to
know a ring snake from an adder or a poisonous from an edible toadstool is a
kind of knowledge that also has practical value.
The grammar of
Mathematics begins, of course, with the multiplication table, which, if not
learnt now, will never be learnt with pleasure; and with the recognition of
geometrical shapes and the grouping of numbers. These exercises lead naturally
to the doing of simple sums in arithmetic. More complicated mathematical
processes may, and perhaps should, be postponed, for the reasons which will
presently appear.
So far (except, of course, for the Latin), our
curriculum contains nothing that departs very far from common practice. The
difference will be felt rather in the attitude of the teachers, who must look
upon all these activities less as subjects in themselves than as a
gathering-together of material for use in the next part of the Trivium. What
that material is, is only of secondary importance; but it is as well that
anything and everything which can be usefully committed to memory should be
memorized at this period, whether it is immediately intelligible or not. The
modern tendency is to try and force rational explanations on a childs
mind at too early an age. Intelligent questions, spontaneously asked, should,
of course, receive an immediate and rational answer; but it is a great mistake
to suppose that a child cannot readily enjoy and remember things that are
beyond his power to analyzeparticularly if those things have a strong
imaginative appeal (as, for example, Kubla Kahn), an attractive
jingle (like some of the memory-rhymes for Latin genders), or an abundance of
rich, resounding polysyllables (like the Quicunque vult).
This reminds
me of the grammar of Theology. I shall add it to the curriculum, because
theology is the mistress-science without which the whole educational structure
will necessarily lack its final synthesis. Those who disagree about this will
remain content to leave their pupils education still full of loose ends.
This will matter rather less than it might, since by the time that the tools of
learning have been forged the student will be able to tackle theology for
himself, and will probably insist upon doing so and making sense of it. Still,
it is as well to have this matter also handy and ready for the reason to work
upon. At the grammatical age, therefore, we should become acquainted with the
story of God and Man in outlinei.e., the Old and New Testaments presented
as parts of a single narrative of Creation, Rebellion, and Redemptionand
also with the Creed, the Lords Prayer, and the Ten Commandments. At this
early stage, it does not matter nearly so much that these things should be
fully understood as that they should be known and remembered.
It is
difficult to say at what age, precisely, we should pass from the first to the
second part of the Trivium. Generally speaking, the answer is: so soon as the
pupil shows himself disposed to pertness and interminable argument. For as, in
the first part, the master faculties are Observation and Memory, so, in the
second, the master faculty is the Discursive Reason. In the first, the exercise
to which the rest of the material was, as it were, keyed, was the Latin
grammar; in the second, the key- exercise will be Formal Logic. It is here that
our curriculum shows its first sharp divergence from modern standards. The
disrepute into which Formal Logic has fallen is entirely unjustified; and its
neglect is the root cause of nearly all those disquieting symptoms which we
have noted in the modern intellectual constitution. Logic has been discredited,
partly because we have come to suppose that we are conditioned almost entirely
by the intuitive and the unconscious. There is no time to argue whether this is
true; I will simply observe that to neglect the proper training of the reason
is the best possible way to make it true. Another cause for the disfavor into
which Logic has fallen is the belief that it is entirely based upon universal
assumptions that are either unprovable or tautological. This is not true. Not
all universal propositions are of this kind. But even if they were, it would
make no difference, since every syllogism whose major premise is in the form
All A is B can be recast in hypothetical form. Logic is the art of
arguing correctly: If A, then B. The method is not invalidated by
the hypothetical nature of A. Indeed, the practical utility of Formal Logic
today lies not so much in the establishment of positive conclusions as in the
prompt detection and exposure of invalid inference.
Let us now quickly
review our material and see how it is to be related to Dialectic. On the
Language side, we shall now have our vocabulary and morphology at our
fingertips; henceforward we can concentrate on syntax and analysis (i.e., the
logical construction of speech) and the history of language (i.e., how we came
to arrange our speech as we do in order to convey our thoughts).
Our
Reading will proceed from narrative and lyric to essays, argument and
criticism, and the pupil will learn to try his own hand at writing this kind of
thing. Many lessonson whatever subjectwill take the form of
debates; and the place of individual or choral recitation will be taken by
dramatic performances, with special attention to plays in which an argument is
stated in dramatic form.
Mathematicsalgebra, geometry, and the
more advanced kinds of arithmeticwill now enter into the syllabus and
take its place as what it really is: not a separate subject but a
sub- department of Logic. It is neither more nor less than the rule of the
syllogism in its particular application to number and measurement, and should
be taught as such, instead of being, for some, a dark mystery, and, for others,
a special revelation, neither illuminating nor illuminated by any other part of
knowledge.
History, aided by a simple system of ethics derived from
the grammar of theology, will provide much suitable material for discussion:
Was the behavior of this statesman justified? What was the effect of such an
enactment? What are the arguments for and against this or that form of
government? We shall thus get an introduction to constitutional historya
subject meaningless to the young child, but of absorbing interest to those who
are prepared to argue and debate. Theology itself will furnish material for
argument about conduct and morals; and should have its scope extended by a
simplified course of dogmatic theology (i.e., the rational structure of
Christian thought), clarifying the relations between the dogma and the ethics,
and lending itself to that application of ethical principles in particular
instances which is properly called casuistry. Geography and the Sciences will
likewise provide material for Dialectic. But above all, we must not neglect the
material which is so abundant in the pupils own daily life.
There is a delightful passage in Leslie Pauls The Living
Hedge which tells how a number of small boys enjoyed themselves for days
arguing about an extraordinary shower of rain which had fallen in their
towna shower so localized that it left one half of the main street wet
and the other dry. Could one, they argued, properly say that it had rained that
day on or over the town or only in the town? How many drops of water were
required to constitute rain? And so on. Argument about this led on to a host of
similar problems about rest and motion, sleep and waking, est and non est, and
the infinitesimal division of time. The whole passage is an admirable example
of the spontaneous development of the ratiocinative faculty and the natural and
proper thirst of the awakening reason for the definition of terms and exactness
of statement. All events are food for such an appetite.
An
umpires decision; the degree to which one may transgress the spirit of a
regulation without being trapped by the letter: on such questions as these,
children are born casuists, and their natural propensity only needs to be
developed and trainedand especially, brought into an intelligible
relationship with the events in the grown-up world. The newspapers are full of
good material for such exercises: legal decisions, on the one hand, in cases
where the cause at issue is not too abstruse; on the other, fallacious
reasoning and muddleheaded arguments, with which the correspondence columns of
certain papers one could name are abundantly stocked.
Wherever the
matter for Dialectic is found, it is, of course, highly important that
attention should be focused upon the beauty and economy of a fine demonstration
or a well-turned argument, lest veneration should wholly die. Criticism must
not be merely destructive; though at the same time both teacher and pupils must
be ready to detect fallacy, slipshod reasoning, ambiguity, irrelevance, and
redundancy, and to pounce upon them like rats. This is the moment when
precis-writing may be usefully undertaken; together with such exercises as the
writing of an essay, and the reduction of it, when written, by 25 or 50
percent.
It will, doubtless, be objected that to encourage young
persons at the Pert age to browbeat, correct, and argue with their elders will
render them perfectly intolerable. My answer is that children of that age are
intolerable anyhow; and that their natural argumentativeness may just as well
be canalized to good purpose as allowed to run away into the sands. It may,
indeed, be rather less obtrusive at home if it is disciplined in school; and
anyhow, elders who have abandoned the wholesome principle that children should
be seen and not heard have no one to blame but themselves.
Once again,
the contents of the syllabus at this stage may be anything you like. The
subjects supply material; but they are all to be regarded as mere
grist for the mental mill to work upon. The pupils should be encouraged to go
and forage for their own information, and so guided towards the proper use of
libraries and books for reference, and shown how to tell which sources are
authoritative and which are not.
Towards the close of this stage, the
pupils will probably be beginning to discover for themselves that their
knowledge and experience are insufficient, and that their trained intelligences
need a great deal more material to chew upon. The imagination usually
dormant during the Pert age will reawaken, and prompt them to suspect the
limitations of logic and reason. This means that they are passing into the
Poetic age and are ready to embark on the study of Rhetoric. The doors of the
storehouse of knowledge should now be thrown open for them to browse about as
they will. The things once learned by rote will be seen in new contexts; the
things once coldly analyzed can now be brought together to form a new
synthesis; here and there a sudden insight will bring about that most exciting
of all discoveries: the realization that truism is true.
It is
difficult to map out any general syllabus for the study of Rhetoric: a certain
freedom is demanded. In literature, appreciation should be again allowed to
take the lead over destructive criticism; and self-expression in writing can go
forward, with its tools now sharpened to cut clean and observe proportion. Any
child who already shows a disposition to specialize should be given his head:
for, when the use of the tools has been well and truly learned, it is available
for any study whatever. It would be well, I think, that each pupil should learn
to do one, or two, subjects really well, while taking a few classes in
subsidiary subjects so as to keep his mind open to the inter-relations of all
knowledge. Indeed, at this stage, our difficulty will be to keep
subjects apart; for Dialectic will have shown all branches of
learning to be inter-related, so Rhetoric will tend to show that all knowledge
is one. To show this, and show why it is so, is pre-eminently the task of the
mistress science. But whether theology is studied or not, we should at least
insist that children who seem inclined to specialize on the mathematical and
scientific side should be obliged to attend some lessons in the humanities and
vice versa. At this stage, also, the Latin grammar, having done its work, may
be dropped for those who prefer to carry on their language studies on the
modern side; while those who are likely never to have any great use or aptitude
for mathematics might also be allowed to rest, more or less, upon their oars.
Generally speaking, whatsoever is mere apparatus may now be allowed to fall
into the background, while the trained mind is gradually prepared for
specialization in the subjects which, when the Trivium is
completed, it should be perfectly will equipped to tackle on its own. The final
synthesis of the Triviumthe presentation and public defense of the
thesisshould be restored in some form; perhaps as a kind of leaving
examination during the last term at school.
The scope of
Rhetoric depends also on whether the pupil is to be turned out into the world
at the age of 16 or whether he is to proceed to the university. Since, really,
Rhetoric should be taken at about 14, the first category of pupil should study
Grammar from about 9 to 11, and Dialectic from 12 to 14; his last two school
years would then be devoted to Rhetoric, which, in this case, would be of a
fairly specialized and vocational kind, suiting him to enter immediately upon
some practical career. A pupil of the second category would finish his
Dialectical course in his preparatory school, and take Rhetoric during his
first two years at his public school. At 16, he would be ready to start upon
those subjects which are proposed for his later study at the
university: and this part of his education will correspond to the mediaeval
Quadrivium. What this amounts to is that the ordinary pupil, whose formal
education ends at 16, will take the Trivium only; whereas scholars will take
both the Trivium and the Quadrivium.
Is the Trivium, then, a
sufficient education for life? Properly taught, I believe that it should be. At
the end of the Dialectic, the children will probably seem to be far behind
their coevals brought up on old-fashioned modern methods, so far as
detailed knowledge of specific subjects is concerned. But after the age of 14
they should be able to overhaul the others hand over fist. Indeed, I am not at
all sure that a pupil thoroughly proficient in the Trivium would not be fit to
proceed immediately to the university at the age of 16, thus proving himself
the equal of his mediaeval counterpart, whose precocity astonished us at the
beginning of this discussion. This, to be sure, would make hay of the English
public-school system, and disconcert the universities very much. It would, for
example, make quite a different thing of the Oxford and Cambridge boat
race.
But I am not here to consider the feelings of academic bodies: I
am concerned only with the proper training of the mind to encounter and deal
with the formidable mass of undigested problems presented to it by the modern
world. For the tools of learning are the same, in any and every subject; and
the person who knows how to use them will, at any age, get the mastery of a new
subject in half the time and with a quarter of the effort expended by the
person who has not the tools at his command. To learn six subjects without
remembering how they were learnt does nothing to ease the approach to a
seventh; to have learnt and remembered the art of learning makes the approach
to every subject an open door.
Before concluding these necessarily
very sketchy suggestions, I ought to say why I think it necessary, in these
days, to go back to a discipline which we had discarded. The truth is that for
the last three hundred years or so we have been living upon our educational
capital. The post-Renaissance world, bewildered and excited by the profusion of
new subjects offered to it, broke away from the old discipline
(which had, indeed, become sadly dull and stereotyped in its practical
application) and imagined that henceforward it could, as it were, disport
itself happily in its new and extended Quadrivium without passing through the
Trivium. But the Scholastic tradition, though broken and maimed, still lingered
in the public schools and universities: Milton, however much he protested
against it, was formed by itthe debate of the Fallen Angels and the
disputation of Abdiel with Satan have the tool-marks of the Schools upon them,
and might, incidentally, profitably figure as set passages for our Dialectical
studies. Right down to the nineteenth century, our public affairs were mostly
managed, and our books and journals were for the most part written, by people
brought up in homes, and trained in places, where that tradition was still
alive in the memory and almost in the blood. Just so, many people today who are
atheist or agnostic in religion, are governed in their conduct by a code of
Christian ethics which is so rooted that it never occurs to them to question
it.
But one cannot live on capital forever. However firmly a tradition
is rooted, if it is never watered, though it dies hard, yet in the end it dies.
And today a great numberperhaps the majorityof the men and women
who handle our affairs, write our books and our newspapers, carry out our
research, present our plays and our films, speak from our platforms and
pulpitsyes, and who educate our young peoplehave never, even in a
lingering traditional memory, undergone the Scholastic discipline. Less and
less do the children who come to be educated bring any of that tradition with
them. We have lost the tools of learningthe ax and the wedge, the hammer
and the saw, the chisel and the planethat were so adaptable to all tasks.
Instead of them, we have merely a set of complicated jigs, each of which will
do but one task and no more, and in using which eye and hand receive no
training, so that no man ever sees the work as a whole or looks to the
end of the work.
What use is it to pile task on task and prolong
the days of labor, if at the close the chief object is left unattained? It is
not the fault of the teachersthey work only too hard already. The
combined folly of a civilization that has forgotten its own roots is forcing
them to shore up the tottering weight of an educational structure that is built
upon sand. They are doing for their pupils the work which the pupils themselves
ought to do. For the sole true end of education is simply this: to teach men
how to learn for themselves; and whatever instruction fails to do this is
effort spent in vain.
Management Techniques Incorporated
has provided this article archive expressly for Issues, Etc. The articles in
this archive have been formatted converted for internet use, by Management
Techniques, Inc.
Contact MTI
webmaster