Articles and book excerpts used in and referred to on Issues, Etc. |
Five Bad
Ways to Argue About Abortion
by
Scott Klusendorf
Pro-life advocates argue that elective
abortion unjustly takes the life of a defenseless human being. In support of
this conclusion, pro-lifers cite both scientific and philosophic evidence.
Nonetheless, some people ignore the evidence pro-life advocates present and
argue for abortion based on self-interest. That is the lazy way out. If we care
about truth, we will courageously follow the facts wherever they lead. But
there are pitfalls. Here are five common mistakes people make arguing for
abortion
Mistake #1: Confuse objective claims with subjective ones
(or confuse claims about ice cream with claims about truth).
When
pro-life advocates say that abortion is morally wrong because it takes the life
of a defenseless child, they are making a particular type of claim.
Specifically, they are making a moral claim about the rightness or
wrongness of abortion.
Many people, however, misconstrue the kind of
claim the pro-lifer is making in order to respond to one they like better.
Consider the following responses to the statement, Abortion is morally
wrong.
"That's just your view."
On a
recent edition of the television show Politically Incorrect, super model
Kathy Ireland gave a carefully reasoned scientific and philosophic defense of
the pro-life position. The show's host, Bill Maher, shot back with, "Kathy,
that's just your view."
What's wrong with this response? Maher was
confusing a moral claim with a preference claim. But there is a
difference between disliking something (say, for example, a particular flavor
of ice cream) and thinking it is morally wrong. Put simply, when pro-life
advocates say that abortion is morally wrong, they are not saying they
personally dislike abortion or would prefer that people not have
one. Rather, they are saying that elective abortion is objectively wrong
for everyone, regardless of how one feels about it. This is why the popular
bumper sticker "Don't like abortion? Don't have one!" misses the point
entirely. It confuses the two types of claims. Try this: "Don't like slavery?
Don't own one!"
Now it may be the case that pro-life advocates like
Kathy Ireland are mistaken about their claim. Perhaps their evidence that
abortion unjustly takes the life of a defenseless child is weak and
inconclusive. But instead of proving this with facts and arguments, abortion
advocates like Bill Maher ignore the evidence altogether. "Well, that's just
your view." This not only relativizes the pro-lifers claim, it is
intellectually lazy. It attempts to dismiss evidence rather than refute it.
Imagine if I were to say, "There is a pink elephant in the corner of the
room just beneath the window." How should you respond to my claim? Perhaps I'm
mistaken (and chances are I would be), but it would do no good to say, "That's
just your view." The problem is I was not offering an opinion, I was
claiming to be right. To refute me, you must show that my claim is
false. The correct response is to say, "Your evidence is lousy. We looked in
the corner and there is no elephant."
But again, Maher did not do
that. At no point did he challenge her facts and arguments. What he said in
effect was "Go away Kathy. You have your views and I have mine." This was very
condescending because he did not even entertain the possibility that she had
good evidence for her claim. Nor did he acknowledge the type of claim she was
making.
To sum up, Maher was confusing a preference claim with a
distinctly moral one. Preference claims cannot be evaluated as true or false
because they are matters of personal taste. You cannot reasonably argue that
vanilla ice cream is objectively better than chocolate.
But moral
claims are different. They can be evaluated as true or false based on the
evidence. They do not say, This is better tasting, they say, This is right.
Kathy Ireland's claim was, Abortion is wrong because it takes the life of a
defenseless child, and I think I'm right. Maher's glib response did nothing to
refute this.
In fact, one could stop Maher dead in his tracks by
saying, Bill, it's just your view that it's just my view.
"Don't force your morality on me."
A student at a Southern
California college said this to me after I made a case for the pro-life
position in her sociology class. She was in effect saying, Morality is
relative; it's up to me to decide what is right and wrong. We call this
moral relativism, the belief that there are no objective standards of
right and wrong, only personal preferences. Therefore, we should tolerate other
views as being equal to our own.
Relativism, however, is seriously
flawed for at least three reasons. First, it is self-refuting. That is to say,
it cannot live by its own rules. Second, relativists cannot reasonably say that
anything is wrong, including intolerance. Third, it is impossible to live as a
relativist.
1) Relativism is self-refuting--it commits intellectual
suicide. The student said it was wrong for me to force my views on others,
but she could not live with her own rule. Although our dialogue was pleasant,
she clearly tried to force her views on me.
Student: You made some good points in your talk, but you shouldn't force your morality on me or anyone else who wants an abortion. It's our choice, isnt it?
Me: Are you saying I'm wrong?
Student: Im not sure. What do you mean?
Me: Well, you think I'm wrong, don't you? If not, why are you correcting me? And if so, then you're forcing your morality on me, aren't you?
Student: No, I just want to know why you are telling people what they can and cannot do with their lives.
Me: Are you saying I shouldn't do that? That its wrong? If so, then why are you telling me what I can and cannot do? Why are you forcing your morality on me?
Student: (regrouping): Im confused. Look, the simple fact is that pro-choicers are not forcing women to have abortions, but you want to force women to be mothers. If you don't like abortion, don't have one. But you shouldnt force your beliefs on others. All I am saying is that pro-life people should be tolerant of other views.
Me: Is that your view?
Student: Yes.
Me: Why are you forcing it on me? Thats not very tolerant, is it?
Student: What do you mean? I think women should have a choice and you don't. Its your view thats intolerant, wouldnt you say?
Me: Okay, so you think I'm wrong. What is it you want pro-lifers like me to do?
Student: You should let women decide for themselves and tolerate other views.
Me: Tell me, what exactly do pro-choicers believe?
Student: We believe everyone should decide for themselves and tolerate other views.
Me: So you are demanding that pro-lifers become pro-choicers.
Student: What?
Me: With all due respect, heres what I hear you saying. Unless I agree with you, you will not tolerate my view. Privately, you'll let me think whatever I want, but you don't want me to act as if my view is true. It seems you think tolerance is a virtue if and only if people agree with you.
Put succinctly, her argument for tolerance
was in fact a patronizing form of intolerance. She spoke of moral neutrality,
but tried to force her views on me.
A recent editorial in the
Toronto Star was similarly intolerant of pro-life advocates. While
decrying the "single-minded moral supremacism" of those who call abortion
killing, journalist Michele Landsberg writes:
Will no priest or minister publicly resolve to stop the indoctrination of youth to view abortion as murder? Is none ashamed of the blood-drenched holocaust vocabulary used so cynically (and anti-semitically) to whip up fervor for the crusade? Where are the outspoken cries of conscience by bishops and cardinals who should be appalled by the evidence of links between anti-abortion fanatics and far-right militias, neo Nazis, and white supremacists? Is there no religious leader who regrets his church's role in feeding this blind frenzy? Will none of them repent of their excesses, will none call a halt to their sickeningly manipulative campaigns of "precious little feet," their fake "documentaries" about screaming fetuses? You'd think that the world had enough lessons in the dangers of hate speech.
Like hers? It doesn't seem to trouble Ms. Landsberg that her own vitriolic rhetoric could incite pro-choicers to commit acts of violence against pro-lifers. She continues:
It was the unbridled hate speech of fundamentalist fanatics in Israel who spurred on the "devout" murder of then-Prime Minister Yitzhak Rabin....We've seen how homophobic rantings from right-wing American leaders, notably the Senate republican leader, led to escalating gay bashings, culminating in the heart- wrenching death of Matthew Shepherd in Wyoming....Denominational schools [should] begin to teach respect for the laws of our pluralistic society, rather than preaching single-minded moral supremacism.
Again, like her own?
Notice what is
going on here. She decries "moral supremacism," but says that anyone who
disagrees with her view on abortion is an indoctrinator of youth, a fanatic, an
anti-Semite, a neo-Nazi, a white supremacist, a manipulator of facts, a
purveyor of hate speech, homophobic, a gay-basher, a religious bully,
responsible for the death of Matthew Shepherd, and finally, a fundamentalist
fanatic like those who murdered Yitzhak Rabin.
One can hardly imagine
a finer piece of self-refuting rhetoric. All, of course, in the name of
tolerance.
While driving my sons to a recent baseball game at Dodger
Stadium, a young woman in a white pickup truck began tailgating me. Visibly
angered by a pro-life sticker on my rear window, she stayed on my bumper for a
mile or so. Finally, she pulled beside me and extended a certain part of her
anatomy skyward as she passed. She then cut in front of me.
At that
moment, I noticed a bumper sticker on her truck. It said, "Celebrate
Diversity." The message was clear: In a pluralistic society, we should tolerate
the views of others. Ironically, the driver saw no contradiction between her
unwillingness to tolerate (or celebrate) my point of view and her bumper
sticker that said we should tolerate all points of view. That is what I
mean when I say that relativism is self-refuting.
2) It is
impossible for a moral relativist to say that anything is wrong, including
intolerance. If morals are relative, then who are you to say that I should
be tolerant? Perhaps my individual morality says intolerance is just fine. Why,
then, should I allow anyone to force tolerance on me as a virtue if my
preference is intolerance?
The truth is, a moral relativist cannot
legitimately say that anything is wrong or truly evil. My colleague Greg Koukl
once challenged a relativist with this question. "Do you think it is wrong to
torture babies for fun?" She paused, then replied, "Well, I wouldn't want to do
that to my baby." Greg responded, "That's not what I asked you. I didn't ask if
you liked torturing babies for fun, I asked if it was wrong to
torture babies for fun." The relativist was caught and she knew it. She
chuckled and went on to another subject.
If it is up to us to decide
(rather than discover) right and wrong, then there is no difference between
Mother Theresa's morality and Adolf Hitler's morality. Hitler was not evil, he
just had preferences different from our own.
3) It is impossible
to live as a moral relativist. As C.S. Lewis points out, a person who
claims there is no objective morality will complain if you break a promise or
cut in line. And if you steal his stereo, he will protest loudly. If I were a
crook, I would reply to the relativist, Do you think stealing stereos is wrong?
Well, that's just your view. My morality says it's perfectly acceptable. Who
are you to force your views on me? Simply put, moral relativists espouse a view
they cannot live with.
"I'm personally opposed to
abortion, but I still think it should be legal."
When people
say this, I ask a simple question to clarify things. I ask why they
personally oppose abortion. Invariably, they reply, We oppose it because it
kills a human baby. At that point, I merely repeat back their words. "Let me
see if I got this straight. You oppose abortion because it kills babies, but
you think it should be legal to kill babies?"
Would these same people
argue that while they personally opposed slavery, they would not protest if a
neighbor wanted to own one? This was precisely what Stephen Douglas did during
his debates with Abraham Lincoln. That argument did not work with slavery and
it will not work with abortion. Either elective abortion kills a defenseless
child or not. If it does, we should not tolerate it. Period.
Mistake #2: Attack the person rather than refute the argument. (Ad
hominem fallacy)
Instead of defending the abortion act itself,
some "pro-choice" advocates personally attack those who do not share their
views. At a 1995 "Rock for Choice" concert in Pensacola Florida, vocalist Eddie
Vedder of Pearl Jam shrieked from the stage: "I'm usually good about my temper,
but all these men trying to control women's bodies really piss me off. They're
talking from a bubble. They're not talking from the street, and they're not in
touch with what's real. Well, I'm f----ing mean, and I'm ugly, and my name is
reality. Music--that is my religion. I would never force my beliefs on
anyone--that's the thing."
During an HBO special, comedian Rosanne
Barr told the audience: "You know who else I can't stand is them people that
are antiabortion....I hate them. They're ugly, old, geeky, hideous men. They
just don't want nobody to have an abortion, cause they want you to keep
spitting out kids so they can molest them."
Do you see what is
happening here? Instead of defending their views with facts and arguments,
Rosanne Barr and Eddie Vedder are attacking the character of pro-lifers. We
call this the ad hominem fallacy. It is fallacious reasoning because
even if the personal attack is true, it does nothing to refute the pro-lifer's
argument.
Let's grant, for the sake of discussion, that pro-life
advocates are hideous old men who molest children, as Roseanne Barr contends is
true. How does this in any way refute the pro-life claim that abortion takes
the life of a defenseless child? Clearly, it does not. The attack is therefore
irrelevant to the argument the pro-life advocate is making.
Consider also the claim that pro-lifers are hypocritical to protest abortion
unless they adopt babies they do not want aborted. For the moment, let's assume
there are not two million American families willing to do this, as is the case.
How would the alleged reluctance of pro-lifers to adopt babies justify the act
of abortion? While it is true that pro-life advocates should help those facing
crisis pregnancies, it is not true that abortion is justified whenever that
obligation is left unmet.
Imagine a bigot arguing, Unless you agree to
marry my wife, you have no right to oppose me beating her. Or, Unless you are
willing to adopt my three sons by noon today, I shall execute them. If you
reject his ultimatum, is he morally justified performing acts of violence on
innocent victims?
Sometimes people are attacked for their gender. Men
are told, "You can't get pregnant, so leave the abortion issue to women."
Besides its obvious sexism, the statement is seriously flawed for several
reasons.
First, arguments do not have genders, people do. Since many
pro-life women use the same arguments offered by pro-life men, it behooves the
abortion advocate to answer these arguments without fallaciously attacking a
person's gender.
Second, to be consistent with their own reasoning,
abortion advocates would have to concede that Roe v. Wade was bad
law--after all, it was decided by nine men. They must also call for the
dismissal of all male lawyers working for Planned Parenthood, the ACLU, etc.,
on abortion related issues. Since abortion advocates are unwilling to do this,
we can restate their argument as follows: "No man can speak on abortion--unless
he agrees with us." Once again, this is a classic case of intolerance.
Third, lesbians and post-menopausal women cannot naturally get pregnant; must
they be silent on the issue?
Finally, think of the bizarre rules we
could derive from this argument:
"Since only generals understand battle, only they should discuss the morality of war."
"Because female sportscasters have never experienced a groin injury, they have no right to broadcast football games on national television."
"Only Jewish people have a right to condemn the holocaust."
Again, abortion advocates must offer facts
and arguments in support of their position. Attacking people personally, even
if those attacks are true, will not make their case or refute ours.
Mistake #3 : Assume what you are trying to prove.
Advocates of
elective abortion must show that the unborn are not fully human or their case
crumbles. But instead of proving this conclusion with facts and arguments, many
people simply assume it within the course of their rhetoric. We call this
"begging the question" and it is a logical fallacy that lurks behind many
arguments for abortion.
A person begs the question when he assumes
what he is trying to prove. Imagine you are undergoing an IRS audit. If federal
prosecutors were to ask, Have you stopped cheating on your taxes?, your defense
lawyer would strongly object. The reason is simple: The question assumes you
have broken the law, the very point prosecutors are trying to prove. Your
attorney would rightly demand they prove guilt with facts and evidence, rather
than assume it with rhetoric.
Arguing that abortion is justified
because a woman has a right to control her own body assumes there is only one
body involved--that of the woman. But this is precisely the point abortion
advocates try to prove. Hence, they beg the question.
Or, take the
claim that no one knows when life begins, therefore abortion should remain
legal. But to argue that no one knows when life begins, and that abortion must
remain legal through all nine months of pregnancy, assumes that life does not
begin until birth--the exact point abortion advocates try to prove. This is
hardly a neutral position. It is a clear case of begging the question.
So is the coat hanger argument, which states that women will die from illegal
abortions if laws are passed protecting the unborn. But unless you begin with
the assumption that the unborn are not human, you are making the highly
questionable claim that because some people die attempting to kill others, the
state should make it safe and legal for them to do so. Should we legalize bank
robbery so it is safer for felons?
If you think a particular argument
begs the question regarding the status of the unborn, simply ask, Would this
justification for abortion also work as a justification for killing toddlers or
other humans? If not, the argument assumes the unborn are not fully human.
Again, it may be the case that the unborn are not fully human and abortion
is therefore justified. But this must be proven with facts and evidence, not
merely assumed by one's rhetoric.
Mistake #4: Confuse
functioning as a person with being a person.
Abortion advocates like Mary Anne Warren claim that a "person" is a living
entity with feelings, self-awareness, and the ability to interact with his or
her environment. Because the fetus, she alleges, can do none of these things,
it cannot be fully human. Warren is espousing a doctrine known as
functionalism, the belief that human beings are defined by what they can and
cannot do. Functionalism, however, is seriously flawed because it fails to make
a number of critical distinctions.
First, one can fail to
function as a person and yet still be a person. People under
anesthesia or in a deep sleep cannot feel pain, are not self-aware, and cannot
reason. Neither can those in reversible comas. But we do not call into question
their humanity because we recognize that although they cannot function
as persons, they still have the being of persons, which is the
essential thing.
Here is the key question: How many functions can I
lose and still be myself? If I lose my sight, am I still me? If my legs and
arms are lost, am I still me? If I cannot speak or hear, am I still me? What if
I can no longer play chess or think critically? What if my IQ is less than 50?
Wouldn't I still be a person with value?
Do I, as a person, become
disposable simply because I cannot do everything you can? Do I lose the right
to live because I am helpless and dependent? Do stronger, more capable people
have more rights than others?
The answer is obviously no. No physical
change or loss of function will cause you to cease being you unless that
change ends your life. When a living thing like the unborn human comes into
being, it remains what it is regardless of the shape of its body or present
capabilities.
Second, one must be a person in order to function as
one. Non-sentient frogs do not become persons simply by acquiring sentience
(the ability to feel pain, etc.). Nor do robots become persons by assembling
cars or loading freight. Rather, a person is one with the natural, inherent
capacity to perform personal acts, even if that capacity is currently
unrealized. One grows in the ability to perform personal acts only because one
already is the kind of thing that grows into the ability to perform personal
acts, i.e., a person.
Third, the rights of individuals in our society
are not based on their current (actual) capacities, but on their
inherent capacities. This sounds complex, but we make this distinction
all the time. For example, no one doubts that newborn humans have fewer actual
capacities than do day-old calves. Baby humans are rather unimpressive in terms
of environmental awareness, mobility, etc. Yet this does not lead us to believe
that the calf belongs in the nursery while the infant can be left in the barn.
To the contrary, we understand that although the infant currently lacks many
functional abilities, it nonetheless has the inherent capacity to function as a
person. But if individual rights are grounded in one's current capacities,
calves should enjoy a greater moral status than do newborns.
People
who are unconscious cannot presently function as persons, but they still have
the inherent capacity to perform personal acts. That is why we do not kill
them. From the moment of conception, the unborn human has the natural, inherent
capacity to function as a person. What he lacks is the current capacity to do
so. That he cannot yet speak, reason, or perform personal acts means only that
he cannot yet function as a person, not that he lacks the essential being of a
person.
This same emphasis on inherent (as opposed to actual) capacity
is underscored in the accepted bio-ethical criteria for brain death. Say, for
example, you have an automobile accident that leaves you in a coma. Some of
your friends think your quality of life is gone and want to unplug life
support. Others, like your parents, rally to stop them. What should be done?
The law in this case is very specific. According to the Uniform
Determination of Death Act written into the health and safety codes of each
state, the deciding factor is not your current state of brain function, but
your inherent state of brain function. For death to occur, there must be an
"irreversible cessation of all functions of the entire brain, including
the brain stem." Hence, the reversibly comatose are never classified as
"non-persons" under our existing legal system despite their current lack of
brain function.
Again, from the moment of conception the unborn entity
has the inherent capacity to have a functioning brain. What it lacks is the
current capacity. Hence, there is no ethical difference between it and the
reversibly comatose, the momentarily unconscious, etc., who enjoy the
protection of law despite their current inability to function as persons.
Finally, functionalism dehumanizes not only the unborn, but also many
people outside of the womb.
Last month, an attorney friend I was
debating argued that until the 32nd week of pregnancy, the unborn's brain
resembles a fish or amphibian in its evolutionary development. Therefore, the
unborn are not fully human until the final stages of pregnancy.
This
argument is dangerous. Darwin and his followers used it a century ago to
dehumanize women. Their contention was that women were biologically and
intellectually inferior because their brains were less developed than a man's.
In The Descent of Man in Relation to Sex, Darwin wrote:
[Man] attains a higher eminence, in whatever he takes up, than can women--whether requiring deep thought, reason, or imagination, or merely the use of the senses and hands. If two lists were made of the most eminent men and women in poetry, history, painting, sculpture, music (inclusive of both composition and performance), history, science, and philosophy, the two lists would not bear comparison. We may also infer, from the law of the deviation from averages...[that] the average mental power in man must be above that of women.
Ladies, it gets worse. In his book The Mismeasure of Man, prominent paleontologist Stephen Jay Gould quotes Darwin disciple Gustave Le Bon as follows:
[Even in] the most intelligent races [there] are large numbers of women whose brains are closer in size to those of gorillas than to the most developed male brains. This inferiority is so obvious that no one can contest it for a moment; only its degree is worth discussion. Women represent the most inferior forms of human evolution and...are closer to children and savages than to an adult, civilized man. They excel in fickleness, inconstancy, absence of thought and logic, and incapacity to reason. Without a doubt, there exists some distinguished women, very superior to the average man, but they are as exceptional as the birth of any monstrosity, as for example, of a gorilla with two heads. Consequently, we may neglect them entirely.
Ladies and gentlemen, what will it be? Will
we acknowledge the truth found in The Declaration of Independence
that human beings have value simply because they are human? Or will we join
Darwin in saying only the achievers, intelligent, and powerful count as full
human persons? Be careful how you decide. The results could one day disqualify
you as human.
Mistake #5: Disguise your true position by appealing
to the hard cases.
Some people argue that legal abortion protects
rape victims from compulsory motherhood. They castigate pro-lifers as cruel and
insensitive toward women suffering assault.
This seems like a powerful
objection. Rape is profoundly evil. Victims deserve our best care. But
theres a moral consideration as well. Does rape involve two victims or
just one? And if the unborn entity involved is human, why should she be forced
to give up her life so that her mother can feel better?
Put
differently, can you think of any other case where, having been victimized
yourself, you can justly turn around and victimize another completely innocent
person? Say, for example, a drunk driver plows into your parked car, destroying
it. To ease the pain of your loss, you take a sledgehammer to your
neighbors sedan. Is this morally permissible? If a friend protests your
actions, is he insensitive? Hardly. So again, the issue is not, Are pro-lifers
cruel?, but, What is the unborn? If the unborn is human, it should not be
killed to benefit its mother. There is no moral complexity here.
But
the appeal to hard cases is flawed in another way that has nothing to do with
one's attitude toward women or the morality of abortion. It is flawed because
it is not entirely truthful.
Here's why. The "pro-choice" position is
not that abortion should be legal only when a woman is raped, but that abortion
is a fundamental right she can exercise for any reason she wants during all
nine months of pregnancy. Instead of defending this position with facts and
arguments, many disguise it with an emotional appeal to rape.
But this
will not make their case. The argument from rape, if successful at all, would
only justify abortion in cases of sexual assault, not for any reason the woman
deems fit. In fact, arguing for abortion-on-demand from the hard case of rape
is like trying to argue for the elimination of all traffic laws because a
person might have to break one rushing a loved one to the hospital. Proving an
exception does not prove a rule.
To expose their smokescreen, I ask
abortion advocates the following: "Okay, I'm going to grant for the sake of
discussion that we keep abortion legal in cases of rape. Will you join me in
supporting legal restrictions on those abortions done for convenience which, as
your own studies show, make up the overwhelming percentage of abortions?"
The answer is almost always no, to which I reply, "Then why did you bring
rape up except to mislead us into thinking you support abortion only in the
hard cases?"
Again, if pro-choicers think abortion should be legal for
all nine months of pregnancy for any reason whatsoever, including sex-selection
and convenience, they should defend that view with facts and arguments. Cashing
in on the tragedy of rape victims is intellectually dishonest.
VI.
Summary and Conclusion:
To sum up, one must show that the unborn
are not fully human or the case for elective abortion crumbles. Scaring people
over illegal abortions or alleged invasions of privacy will not make the case.
No privacy argument is a legitimate cover for a conspiracy to do serious harm
to an innocent human being.
The fact that some people controvert a
position does not make that position intrinsically controversial. People argued
for both sides about slavery, racism and genocide, but that did not make them
complex issues.
No, we can do better than that. Abortion is complex
only for those who, because of their own self-interest, want to make it
complex. To paraphrase what Abraham Lincoln said to Stephen Douglas, You do not
have a right to do what is wrong.
Scott
Klusendorf is Director of Bio-Ethics at Stand to Reason.
The preceding excerpt "Five Bad Ways to Argue About Abortion"
© 1997, is from Scott Klusendorf's book "Pro-Life 101: a User Friendly
Guide to Making Your Case on Campus". Permission granted to copy for personal
use only.
To order his book "Pro-Life 101: a User Friendly Guide to
Making Your Case on Campus", contact
STR or call
310-539-3932.
Management Techniques Incorporated
has provided this article archive expressly for Issues, Etc. The articles in
this archive have been formatted converted for internet use, by Management
Techniques, Inc.
Contact MTI
webmaster